Some Metatheorems

8 Some Metatheorems

8.1 Replacement, negation and duality, prenex normal form

8.1.1 Φ^{α_1, α_2, …,α_n}_{β_1,β_2, …,β_n} : For any formula Φ, result of replacing all free occurrences of distinct variables (α_1, α_2, …,α_n) by occurrences of individual symbols (β_1,β_2, …,β_n) respectively.

8.1.2 String of quantifiers : a quantifier | result of prefixing a quantifier to a shorter string of quantifiers

8.1.2.1 A string of universal quantifiers : a universal quantifier | result of prefixing a universal quantifier to a shorter string of quantifiers

8.1.2.2 A string of existential quantifiers : an existential quantifier | result of prefixing an existential quantifier to a shorter string of quantifiers

8.1.3 Closure of formula Ψ (a formula Φ) : Φ is sentence and Φ = Ψ or Φ is the result of prefixing a string of universal quantifiers to Ψ

8.1.4 \(\Vdash\)Φ : every closure of Φ is a theorem of logic

8.1.5 ( I )If Φ^{α_1, α_2, …,α_n}_{β_1,β_2, …,β_n} is a theorem of logic (where β_1,β_2, …,β_n are distinct individual constants not occurring in Φ) , then\(\Vdash\)Φ

8.1.5.1 Pf) UG

8.1.6 ( II )If one closure of Φ is a theorem of logic, then \(\Vdash\)Φ

8.1.6.1 Pf) US

8.1.7 ( III )If \(\Vdash\)Φ and \(\Vdash\)Φ \(\implies) Ψ, then \(\Vdash\)Ψ

8.1.7.1 Pf) US

8.1.8 ( IV )Generalization

8.1.8.1 \(\Vdash\)(α)(α’)Φ \(\iff\) (α)(α’)Φ

8.1.8.2 \(\Vdash\)(∃α)(∃α’)Φ \(\iff\) (∃α)(∃α’)Φ

8.1.8.3 \(\Vdash\)(α)(Φ & Ψ) \(\iff\) (Φ & (α)Ψ) if α does not occur free in Φ

8.1.8.4 \(\Vdash\)(α)(∃α’)(Φ & Ψ) \(\iff\) ((α)Φ & (∃α’)Ψ) if α does not occur free in Φ

8.1.9 ( V ) If \(\Vdash\)Ψ\(\iff\)Ψ’, then

8.1.9.1 \(\Vdash\)-Ψ\(\iff\)-Ψ

8.1.9.2 \(\Vdash\)(Ψ & χ) \(\iff\) (Ψ’ & χ)

8.1.9.3 \(\Vdash\)( χ & Ψ ) \(\iff\) ( χ & Ψ’ )

8.1.9.4 \(\Vdash\) ( Ψ V χ ) \(\iff\) ( Ψ’ V χ )

8.1.9.5 \(\Vdash\) ( χ V Ψ ) \(\iff\) ( χ V Ψ’ )

8.1.9.6 \(\Vdash\) (Ψ \(\implies) χ) \(\iff\) (Ψ’\(\implies)χ)

8.1.9.7 \(\Vdash\) (χ \(\implies) Ψ) \(\iff\) (χ \(\implies)Ψ’)

8.1.9.8 \(\Vdash\) (Ψ \(\iff\) χ) \(\iff\) (Ψ’ \(\iff\) χ)

8.1.9.9 \(\Vdash\) (χ \(\iff\) Ψ) \(\iff\) ( χ \(\iff\) Ψ’)

8.1.9.10 \(\Vdash\) (α)Ψ \(\iff\) (α)Ψ’

8.1.9.11 \(\Vdash\) (∃α)Ψ \(\iff\) (∃α)Ψ

8.1.9.11.1 pf) I, III, IV

8.1.10 (Replacement)

8.1.10.1 Suppose that Φ’ is like Φ except for containing an occurrence of Ψ’ where Φ contains an occurrence of Ψ, and suppose that \(\Vdash\)Ψ\(\iff\)Ψ’. Then \(\Vdash\)Φ\(\iff\)Φ’, and \(\Vdash\)Φ iff \(\Vdash\)Φ’

8.1.10.1.1 Pf) V, I, III

8.1.11 (Definition of equivalence) : for any formulas Φ and Ψ, Φ is equivalent to Ψ iff \(\Vdash\)Φ\(\iff\)Ψ

8.1.12 (Rewriting of bound variables) if formulas (α)Φ and (α’)Φ’ are alike except that former has occurrences of α where and only where the latter has occurrences of α’, then they are equivalent. Similarly for (∃α)Φ and (∃α’)Φ’.

8.1.12.1 Pf) I

8.1.13 (Negation theorem) Suppose that a formula Φ contains no occurrences of \(\implies) and \(\iff\) and that Φ’ is obtained from Φ by exchanging & and v, exchanging universal and the corresponding existential quantifiers, and by repacing atomic formulas by their negations. Then Φ’ is equivalent to -Φ.

8.1.14 (Definition of Prenex normal form) ( a formula Φ ) : Φ is either quantifier-free or consists of a string of quantifiers followed by a quantifier-free formula.

8.1.15 (Prenex normal form) : For any formula Φ there is an equivalent formula Ψ that is in prenex normal form.

8.1.15.1 Pf) reduction to prenex normal form, (Replacement), (Negation theorem), IV

8.1.15.2 If a sentence Φ has a prenex normal form in the prefix of which no existential quantifier precedes any universal quantifier, then the validity of Φ is decidable.

8.1.16 (X) if \(\Vdash\)Φ and if Ψ is the result of replacing all atomic formulas in Φ by their negations, then \(\Vdash\)Ψ

8.1.17 (Duality) if \(\Vdash\)Φ\(\iff\)Ψ and neither \(\implies) nor \(\iff\) occurs in Φ and Ψ, and if Φ* and Ψ* are obtained from Φ and Ψ, respectively, by exchanging & and v, and universal and the corresponding existential quantifiers, then \(\Vdash\)Φ\(\iff\)Ψ ; similarly if \(\Vdash\)Φ\(\iff\)Ψ, then \(\Vdash\)Ψ* \(\implies) Φ*

8.1.17.1 Pf) (Replacement), (Negation theorem), (X)

8.2 Soundness and consistency

8.2.1 Sound ( a system of inference rules) : any conclusion derived by their use will be a consequence of the premises from which it is obtained

8.2.1.1 Assertion

8.2.1.1.1 Any sentence appearing on the first line of a derivation is a consequence of the premises of that line

8.2.1.1.2 Any sentence appearing on the latter line is a consequence of its premises if all sentences appearing on earlier lines are consequence of theirs

8.2.1.2 Any sentence appearing on a line of a derivation is a consequence of the premises of that line

8.2.1.3 If a sentence Φ is derivable from a set of sentences Γ, then Φ is a consequence of Γ.

8.2.2 Consistent ( a system of inference rules ) : there is no sentence Φ such that both Φ and -Φ are derivable from (Universal set)

8.2.2.1 Transform T(Φ) (a sentence Φ) : SC sentence which is the result of deleting all individual symbols, quantifiers, and predicate superscripts from Φ

8.3 Completeness

8.3.1 Complete ( a system of inference rules ) : One can derive, from any given set of sentences, any consequence of that set

8.3.1.1 Consistent with respect to derivability ( a set of sentences Γ ) : the sentence ‘P&-P’ is not derivable from Γ ~ d-consistent

8.3.1.1.1 For any sentence Φ and set of sentences Γ, Φ is derivable form Γ iff ΓU{-Φ} is not d-consistent

8.3.1.1.2 For any set of sentences Γ, Γ is d-consistent iff at least one sentence Φ from L is not derivable from Γ

8.3.1.2 Maximal d-consistent (a set of sentences Γ) iff Γ is d-consistent and not properly included in any d-consistent set Δ.

8.3.1.2.1 Φ€Δ iff -Φ !∈ Δ

8.3.1.2.2 Φ∈Δ iff Φ is derivable from Δ

8.3.1.2.3 (Φ v Ψ) ∈ Δ iff Φ ∈ Δ or Ψ ∈ Δ

8.3.1.2.4 (Φ & Ψ) ∈ Δ iff Φ ∈ Δ and Ψ ∈ Δ

8.3.1.2.5 (Φ \(\implies) Ψ) ∈ Δ iff Φ !∈ Δ or Ψ ∈ Δ, or both

8.3.1.2.6 (Φ \(\iff\) Ψ) ∈ Δ iff Φ, Ψ ∈ Δ or Φ, Ψ !∈ Δ

8.3.1.3 ω-complete ( a set of sentences Γ ) : for every formula Φ and variable α, if (∃α)Φ belongs to Γ, then there is an individual constant β s.t. Φ α/β also belongs to Γ.

8.3.1.4 Suppose Δ is maximal d-consistent and ω-complete, then

8.3.1.4.1 (α)Φ ∈ Δ iff for every individual constant β, Φ α/β ∈ Δ

8.3.1.4.2 (∃α)Φ ∈ Δ iff for some individual constant β, Φ α/β ∈ Δ

8.3.2 Principle lemma for completeness

8.3.2.1 ( I ) for any set of sentences Γ, if Γ is d-consistent, then it is consistent.

8.3.2.1.1 ( I’ ) for any set of sentences Γ, if Γ is d-consistent and all indices of individual constants occurring in the sentences of Γ are even, then it is consistent.

8.3.2.1.2 ( II ) For any set of sentences Γ, if Γ satisfies the hypothesis of I’, then there is a set of sentences Δ that includes Γ and is maximal d-consistent and ω-complete.

8.3.2.1.2.1 Assume that all the sentences of L can be arranged in an infinite list Φ_1, Φ_2, … Φ_n with following properties.

8.3.2.1.2.1.1 Each sentence of L occurs at least one in the list

8.3.2.1.2.1.2 For each sentence of the form (∃α)Φ, there is at least one I such that Φ_i = (∃α)Φ and Φ_(i+1) = Φ α/β, where β is a ‘new’ individual constant

8.3.2.1.3 ( III ) every maximal d-consistent, ω-complete set of sentences is consistent.

8.3.2.1.3.1 Corollary : every maximal d-consistent ,ω-complete set of sentences is satisfiable by an interpretation having a domain equinumerous with the positive integers. ( denumerably infinite domain)

8.3.2.1.4 Corollary of ( I ) : For any set of sentences Γ, if Γ is d-consistent, then it is satisfiable by an interpretation having a denumerably infinite domain.

8.3.2.1.5 (Löwenheim-Skolem theorem) : if Γ is a consistent set of sentences, then Γ is satisfiable by an interpretation having a denumerably infinite domain.

8.4 A proof procedure for valid sentences

8.4.1 If a given sentence is valid, then there exists procedures which generates a proof of that sentence.

8.4.1.1 Given an arbitrary valid sentence Φ, we can reduce Φ to a sentence Ψ in prenex normal form.

8.4.1.2 Procedure ( a valid sentence Φ in prenex normal form ) :

8.4.1.2.1 Enter -Φ on the first line as a premise.

8.4.1.2.2 Derive a prenex normal form Ψ from -Φ.

8.4.1.2.3 Construct a sequence of lines satisfying the following two conditions, until a truth-functional inconsistency appears:

8.4.1.2.3.1 Whenever any universal generalization (α)θ appears on a line, particular instances θ α/β (for all individual constants β occurring in the sequence, and in any case for at least one individual constant β) shall appear on later lines, inferred by US.

8.4.1.2.3.2 Whenever any existential generalization (∃α)θ appears on a line, θ α/β (for some new individual constant β ) shall appear as a premise on a later line.

8.4.1.2.4 When a truth-functional inconsistency appears, derive ‘P&-P’ by rule T, apply ES to transfer dependence to -Φ, conditionate to obtain the theorem -Φ \(\implies) (P&-P), and apply T to obtain the theorem Φ.